a Complementary Truth, and Sundry Consequences Carmine Gorga November 2015
|
Monday, March 26, 2018
The Creators of Poverty
Toward the Definition of Economic Rights
Journal of Markets &
Morality 2, no. 1(Spring 1999), 88-101
Copyright © 1999 Center for Economic Personalism
Toward the
Definition of Economic Rights
Carmine
Gorga
President
Polis-tics, Incorporated
Introduction
With the assistance of a rigorous analysis of a long sweep of
history by Daniel
Rush Finn,1 the central legal
dilemma of our age can be identified as follows: We either redefine property
rights or we define economic rights. This essay attempts to define economic
rights.
Currently, the terms economic rights, property rights, and entitlements are treated as nearly interchangeable synonyms. We will see that these entities are, in fact, connected to one another by many subtle links of timing sequence and by many overlapping intellectual conditions determining their respective identities. In the process, distinctions will emerge that separate these three entities from each other and firmly implant economic rights within the structure of the theory of justice.
From a practical point of view, the judgment that economic rights are neither entitlements nor the same entity as property rights leads to a fundamental realization. Since no accepted definition of economic rights can be found in theory, there is no rationale for the exercise of economic rights in practice. There is observable evidence of access to economic resources, but, clearly, the fact of access is not the same as the right of access.
The task of defining economic rights assumes particular
importance because these rights occupy a pivotal position in an integrated
system of social thought. They can be conceived not only as the focal point of
economic policy and economic theory, but they can be construed as the keystone
in the arch of economic justice. To anticipate the conclusion of this essay,
only those who exercise economic rights can be said to participate in the
economic process in full dignity and self-reliance.
Toward the Definition of Economic Rights
To clarify issues concerning the definition of economic
rights, it might be useful to begin with an overview of three factual
distinctions between economic rights, property rights, and entitlements. These
distinctions can be taken as facts at this stage of the discussion but they
will be justified in the course of the argument. First, the content of these
three entities is different. The object of property rights are marketable things, tangible or
intangible things such as material goods and services. The object of
entitlements are human needs, from
food to shelter to health. The object of economic rights are economic needs. Second, the legal form
of these three entities is different. Property rights are concrete legal titles over existing wealth; economic rights are abstract legal claims over future
wealth; and entitlements are moral
claims on wealth that legally belong to others. Finally, the quantity that they
measure is variable. While both property rights and entitlements relate to
existing wealth, and therefore a necessarily finite quantity, economic rights
relate to future wealth, an unknown and elastic—if not a potentially
infinite—quantity.
Economic rights can be defined as follows: Economic rights
are rights of access to resources—such
as land, labor, physical, and financial capital—that are essential for the
creation, legal appropriation, and market exchange of goods and services.
Economic rights are self-evident. However, for their full recognition, economic
rights require at least three conditions: (1) they require a knowledge of basic
economic needs for a person to operate in the economic world; (2) they require
a knowledge of their legal characteristics; and (3) they have to be fully
integrated into the theory of justice. This essay attempts to articulate a
framework that satisfies these three conditions.
Basic Economic Needs
The basic economic needs of any human being extend over one
or more functions that are related to the creation, legal appropriation, and
market exchange of goods and services. These needs have traditionally been
satisfied through access to labor and
land, which also includes natural resources. In the modern world, one must
include access to physical as well as financial capital among the prerequisites
of an independent and productive economic life.
There is no economic activity that does not require labor, land, and natural resources to be carried out. No poet or painter, let alone an industrialist, can perform any function without access to these resources. Furthermore, once money is seen as a means of exchange, it will be conceived to include all forms of wealth, whether physical or financial wealth. Then it can be seen how, even in a condition of barter, money is essential to carrying out any market function.
And equally essential to carrying out any economic function today is access to physical capital, whether it is a pen, a computer, or a shovel. In previous times, poets may have subsisted on berries and may have been able to produce their own papyrus on which to scratch their poems. Today, we have restricted our own capabilities through the acquisition of specialized knowledge and so, in order to function properly in the economic sphere, we need access to physical capital that is generally owned by others. To put it restrictively, access to labor, land, natural resources, financial, and physical capital is essential to the performance of any economic function—whether it is production, legal appropriation, or market exchange of wealth. Indeed, access to these resources is essential to the very existence of human life.
This is generally well-known. What is not known—and, if known, not readily granted—is the legal fact that only productive people acquire by right the title to marketable products and services, a title that is independent of other people’s will. And what is openly disputed is the claim that only productive people have the legal as well as the practical means to exchange goods and services in the market. The great tension that exists in the field of entitlements is the attempt to overthrow these basic legal and economic realities.
In accordance with these complex practical and theoretical conditions, four economic rights can be isolated from other potential rights, which must be placed at the foundation of a modern economic policy that is concerned with the production, legal acquisition, and exchange of marketable goods and services. These four rights are formulated in correspondence with the factors of production of classical economic analysis; namely, land, labor, and capital— with capital being specified in both its financial and physical aspects. These rights belong to each human being, and can be expressed in these terms:
• The
right of access to land and natural resources
• The
right of access to national credit
• The
right to own the fruits of one’s labor
• The
right to protect one’s wealth
This system of rights can be subdivided in
a variety of ways. To be established singly and jointly, these rights have to
be justified on many grounds. In some of my earlier work,2
readers can find the contours of the economic, political, and moral rationale
for these rights. Our primary focus here has to do with the legal grounds of
these rights.
Some Legal Characteristics of Economic Rights
Economic rights are rights of access to resources that are
essential for the creation, legal appropriation, and market exchange of goods
and services. In order to obtain a more precise understanding of this
definition, the legal characteristics of economic rights can be pinpointed as
follows.
Economic Rights Distinct From Property Rights
and Entitlements
Economic rights can be clearly distinguished from property
rights, once it has been acknowledged that economic rights are the necessary
precondition for the creation and the legal establishment of property rights
and entitlements. Property rights cannot be
identified with economic rights. Property rights are the bundle of dominion
rights over existing goods and
services that are demanded for the fulfillment of human needs. Economic rights,
on the other hand, are rights of access to resources that are needed to create future goods and services. This
differentiation is transparent when economic resources are not owned by anyone
at the time they are energized to serve in the production process. For
instance, in the process of creating consumer goods, one can fish or hunt for
animals that are still held in the commons, and the only legal tool that one
needs is the right of access to those resources. Moreover, one can make use of
a financial resource such as credit—an entity that manifests itself as the
power to create money not exclusively by a government agency but by private
parties as well. Indeed, by looking deeper into the subject it becomes evident
that the power to create money belongs to the people exclusively, and the role
of government agencies is confined to administering that function properly. The
differentiation between economic rights and property rights holds even when
resources are owned by someone else at the time they are acquired and energized
to serve in the production process. The bundle of legal prerequisites involved
in accessing those resources constitutes the set of economic rights. Thus, the
process of creating new wealth, of legally acquiring ownership or transferring
ownership of wealth, involves the exercise of economic rights. Ownership of
specific items of wealth involves the exercise of property rights. Property
rights are static; economic rights are dynamic. Property rights involve stocks
of wealth; economic rights involve flows of wealth.
Entitlements must be distinguished from economic rights. Entitlements transfer the possession of specific property (e.g., money or things) and property rights from one person to another—forcibly, if necessary, under penalty of retribution from an agency of the state. An example of this power is exercised by the Internal Revenue Service. Entitlements relate to existing wealth.
Both property rights and entitlements have a clear market value and are social to the extent that if society did not exist, property rights not only would not exist but would not be necessary to human existence. Property rights and entitlements are social and alienable, while economic rights are innate and inalienable. Since economic rights are inextricably linked to the basic requirements of life, they accompany the very existence of life; and unless one wants to live the life of enslavement—a condition that is not legally permissible in a civilized society—they are also not alienable. Succinctly put, provided economic rights are in vigorous existence, the denial of an entitlement or a property right would not necessarily imply a denial of the right to life. With due qualifications, singly and jointly, the denial of the right of access to land and natural resources, the denial of the right of access to national credit, the denial of the right to enjoy the fruits of one’s labor, and the denial of the right to protect one’s property, essentially amounts to a denial of the rights to life and liberty, and certainly to the denial of civilized life and liberty.
The major differences between economic rights, property rights, and entitlements can be summarized this way: Economic rights represent a legal claim on potential property rights; property rights represent a legal claim on wealth that is already in existence; and entitlements represent a moral claim on wealth that is legally owned by others.
The Differentiation Between Private Rights and
Public (or Constitutional) Rights
The proposed set of economic rights offers the interesting
theoretical possibility of establishing the category of public rights within the theory of justice. For some reason, the
category of public rights does not exist in any of the texts or the standard
reference books of Anglo-Saxon legal literature. Therefore, it seems that in
order to realize this possibility, we need to go back to Immanuel Kant’s Philosophy of Law,3
where the foundation for the distinction between public and private rights is
clearly defined. However, it is important to realize that Kant left the
category of public rights as an empty set. He concluded his analysis by stating
that “… the Matter of Private Right is, in short, the very same in
both”—namely, in the “sphere of PRIVATE RIGHT” as in the “sphere of
PUBLIC
RIGHT.”4
The acceptance of economic rights would give content to the category of public rights, and would help to differentiate between public and private rights within the field of economic justice. This differentiation would be useful not only in establishing continuity of thought with the range of political freedom where most public rights are fully recognized. The immediate usefulness of the category of public rights would consist in clearly distinguishing property rights from economic rights. Property rights would be categorized as private rights and economic rights as public rights. If the category of public rights were unacceptable for some reason, then economic rights could be classified as constitutional rights.
Another Difference Between Property Rights and Economic Rights
If the distinction between private and public (or
constitutional) rights is accepted, one can further clarify the essential
differences that exist between property rights and economic rights. By
confining property rights to the category of private rights and assigning
economic rights to the category of public (or constitutional) rights, one could
clearly see that property rights regarding a specific item of wealth belong to
us exclusively on either a personal
or an individual basis. Economic rights, instead, are those that belong to
everyone on a universal basis.
To eliminate a potential source of confusion, it is necessary to classify the right to ownership in general as an ancillary economic right and therefore as a public right—a right belonging to everyone. While the right of ownership over a specific piece of property would always be classified as a property right and therefore as a private right, economic rights, instead, would belong exclusively to the category of public (or constitutional) rights.
These are not simply intellectual distinctions. They have a solid foundation in fact. While property rights restrict other peoples’ freedom, because they necessarily exclude people from using specific pieces of property, economic rights enlarge the range of freedom for everyone. Economic rights are similar to voting rights. Voting rights do not restrict the freedom of anyone; rather, they enlarge the range of freedom of everyone.
The Differentiation Between Rights in Posse and
Rights in Esse
Public (or constitutional) rights are potentialities; they
are rights in posse. For example, the
right to vote is a potential right and not the actual act of voting. Public (or
constitutional) rights are recognized by the community on behalf of all its
citizens. Private rights, on the other hand, are granted by the community to
individual persons exclusively. Thus, economic rights are rights in posse and property rights are rights in esse.
In these theoretical questions, the issue of the practical usefulness of economic rights is embedded. Succinctly stated, their usefulness rests on the fact that they represent a legal claim on future property rights. In other words, economic rights, as many other rights, represent legal potentialities. To distinguish them from other rights, these potentialities perform a specific function. They represent opportunities to create wealth. Thus, their exercise allows people to exist in the economic sphere with full dignity and a degree of interdependence. Since, by nature, economic rights are universal they represent a fair distribution of opportunities to create future wealth.
Rights and Responsibilities
From Giuseppe Mazzini5 to Oliver Wendell
Holmes,6 it has been recognized that the very essence of rights is
that they imply responsibilities. There are various reasons for the existence
of an indissoluble link between these two entities. The first reason can be
found in the very nature of rights observed in the full glory of social and
communal relations. If rights are innate, they belong to all human beings
universally. Therefore, since the community does not possess them, when it
assigns them to each individual person—i.e., when their title is conferred by
society—the community must request a quid
pro quo as compensation for all other people. The quid is the responsibility. It is the assignment of
responsibilities that, given community relationships, provides legal legitimacy
to the assignment of rights.
Then there is the issue of moral legitimacy. Society cannot give rights away without simultaneously assigning responsibilities. Responsibilities, so understood, confer moral justification for rights. One justification for this linkage can be found in the domain of political science. David E. Stephens, a moral theologian, once suggested the following to me in a letter: “If one has responsibilities but no corresponding rights, then one is bound by and a victim of necessity—in the form of some kind of tyranny. If one has rights and no corresponding responsibilities, then one is unaccountably free, a state of anarchy.” He went on to make an important philosophical argument: “Yet, in both cases the linkage between right and responsibility is inescapable: If one is bound by necessity, either one has a responsibility to conform to necessity or to suffer the alternative sanctions. If one is unaccountably free, then either one is selfaccountable or self-destructive. Barring destruction of the party or parties in either state, some responsibility or some rights must coordinate with the state of necessity or freedom. Between these polar states, a full spectrum of proportionality of coordinated rights and responsibilities are to be found.”
A society that wants to be civilized must link people together through a set of mutual rights and responsibilities. Human relationships then become legal because they are moral, and they are moral because they are legal. From one perspective, responsibilities are the quid pro quo that diminishes the reasons for society to ever take rights away from individual human beings, and thus binds society to the individual person. From the other side, responsibilities represent what is given back to society, and thus bind the individual person to society. In either case, responsibilities provide the moral justification for rights. If the right balance is found, the statesman builds not only upon a moral foundation but he also ensures stability for the future. Members of society will not desire to alter those relationships.
Corresponding Economic Responsibilities
Responsibilities cannot be superimposed upon rights
arbitrarily. Rather, they are an inherent part of them, and are time- and
place-specific. If the rights are conceptual, then the responsibilities must be
conceptual. Yet, as soon as the exercise of rights becomes concrete, their
inherent obligations become legal
obligations—obligations, that is, enforceable in a court of law.
All too briefly, since the arguments belong mostly to the field of economic analysis and economic policy, the responsibilities that one might want to associate with the four economic rights enunciated above can be pinpointed as follows. In correspondence with the right of access to natural resources, there ought to be the duty to pay taxes for the use of those resources. The basic rationale for this duty is not only that natural resources are a common good and the good of all requires that they be equitably shared, but that the payment of taxes is a token compensation for the exclusion of others from the use of those resources. Furthermore, the rationale is that much—but by no means all—of the value of one’s property derives from communal efforts (e.g., the provision of water, sewer, and electric lines; schools, theaters, and museums). The rationale is also that by paying taxes on land and natural resources one eliminates the incentive to hoard those resources and thus, with full compensation, one makes the resources that are hoarded potentially part of the commonwealth through voluntary market exchanges. The alternative is clear: One can hold on to the land but one must pay taxes on those holdings. Taxes on land and natural resources cannot be construed as “takings.” Quite simply, they represent payment for the provision of public services received directly by the owner of the land. The extent to which taxes on land and natural resources should exceed the value of the public goods received can be ascribed to payment for the social and economic benefits of the absence of hoarding.
In correspondence with the right of access to national credit there ought to be the duty to repay the loan. The exercise of this right should be subjected to the following restrictions: (1) Access should be limited to capital credit to create new wealth (consumer credit, credit for paper transactions, as well as credit for transfer of ownership titles would not qualify); (2) It should be issued to benefit all participants in the enterprise; and (3) It should be issued at cost. The rationale for the basic duty to repay the loan is that national credit is a common good. Failure to repay the loan causes the pool of common resources to be drained. Worse yet, due to inflationary effects, by not repaying the loan one debases the currency to the detriment of everyone—the abuser of the right included.
Corresponding to the third right mentioned above, the right to own the fruits of one’s labor, there ought to be the duty to meet the obligations outlined in the performance of the work. Likewise, corresponding to the right to protect one’s wealth, there ought to be the duty to respect other people’s wealth.
A brief note regarding the implementation of these duties should be appended here. As it can be seen from this list, the obligations are not obligations of the state. If the state does not have economic rights to apportion, it cannot assume economic obligations to fulfill. The obligations flow from individual human beings to other human beings. The state can only administer the policies that make for an easy fulfillment of those obligations.
Theory and Practice
The natural mutuality of interests and concerns among human
beings makes for an integration of rights and responsibilities. We have seen
that this integration is such an essential part of the theory of economic
rights one might conclude that the link forms an implicit contract. However,
does this imply that the theory is always respected in practice? Since the law
does not have a soul, since it does not have an essence of its own, there is no
ultimate justification in the law for this linkage. The justifications we have
found occur in the domain of morality, sociology, politics, and philosophy, but
not in the law. The law is a tool, in fact, a neutral tool of society. In the
end, the law can accomplish anything society wants it to accomplish. Hence,
there is no legal justification for
rights to be tied to responsibilities. Indeed, since rights are social
entities, they are a two-edged sword. Society giveth; society can take away.
Society can only grant privileges. Society cannot grant rights; it can only
recognize them. But society can prevent their exercise.
The link between theory and practice can be dissolved; yet if the link is a natural one, many problems will arise from its dissolution. Rather than the administration of universal rights, one shall find the granting of factional privileges. Rather than the protection of the laws, one shall find a favoritism imposed by force. Rather than freedom for all, one shall find libertinism for the few. Rather than social integration, one shall eventually find social disintegration. Liberty and stability exist only in a regimen of just laws. For moral, sociological, and political reasons it is advisable that rights be indissolubly tied to responsibilities. With such a burden lying on the propriety of the link between rights and responsibilities, one must make sure that the theory is indeed sound.
Economic Rights Within the Theory of Justice
We will examine five tests of legal validity that the
proposed economic rights must pass before they can be accepted as true public
(or constitutional) rights.
Thereafter, we will see whether they conform with established principles of economic justice. Finally, we will see what sort of place they might eventually occupy within the structure of the theory of justice.
Some Theoretical Perspectives
For these rights and responsibilities to be accepted, they
must pass a number of theoretical tests that belong to the legal understanding
of justice. First, do the proposed rights and responsibilities yield the
essential elements of “the original position” envisioned by Rawls?7
Second, do they meet the requirements of the “reverse theory” enunciated by
Nozick?8 Recognizing that “particular rights over things fill the
space of rights, leaving no room for general rights to be in a certain material
condition,” Nozick postulates: “The reverse theory would place only such
universally held general ‘rights to’ achieve goals or to be in a certain
material condition into its substructure so as to determine all else; to my
knowledge no serious attempt has been made to state this ‘reverse’ theory.”9
A third theoretical test of validity can be construed in relation to the Principle of Generic Consistency, which has been carefully designed and cogently argued for by Alan Gewirth.10 Will the above set of four rights and responsibilities pass this test? Gewirth’s principle to “Act in accord with the generic rights of your recipients as well as of yourself”11 is an attempt to synthesize the logical requirements advanced by Rawls with those of Nozick.
There are many other tests of validity. The next that might be considered is based on the conditions for the existence of a “system of rights” as specified by Rex Martin.12 Can those rights function as a system of rights? One final test comes to mind. Are the proposed rights and responsibilities properly “integrated within a robust vision of a very traditional Catholic concern, namely, the common good,” as Finn recommends?13
The Principles of Justice
For the proposed economic rights and responsibilities
eventually to become an integral part of the theory of justice they have to be
expressions of sound legal and philosophical principles. The most important
test that those four rights and responsibilities, singly and jointly, have to
sustain is this: Are those rights built on the basis of solid principles? The
essential principles submitted for scrutiny are:
•
Each specific right shall make us free (the
intellectual, rationalist argu-ment);
•
Each specific right shall be universal (the
idealist as well as the utilitarianargument);
•
Each specific right shall be fair (the
emotional, naturalistic, transcenden-talist argument);
•
Each specific right shall be enforceable in a
court of law (the positivistargument);
•
Each specific right shall create social order
(the political and aesthetic ar-gument).
Only a few questions can be raised here to
point toward the necessary analysis that must be done to determine the
correspondence of those rights with the above principles: (1) Is each one of
those rights intimately related to the question of truth—and hence to freedom
in general—as well as to issues of economic freedom in particular? (2) Is each
one of those rights an expression of universality and even of universal
utilitarianism? (3) Is each one of those rights related to natural rights
theory? (4) Can each right also be justified in terms of positivism? (5) Does
each right have the potentiality to contribute to social as well as
intellectual harmony?
A Place Within the Theory of Justice
If the proposed rights and responsibilities pass the
specific tests of legal validity mentioned above and if they pass the
theoretical test of concordance with basic principles of philosophy, in order
to become fully accepted, they have to occupy a specific place within the
theory of justice. Is there such a place for them?
A place for economic rights and responsibilities within the structure of the theory of justice will be found only if two requirements are met. First, one must adhere to the ancient division of this body of knowledge into two fields: political justice and economic justice. With regard to economic justice, we must add to it a new plank: participative justice.
From Aristotle to the late Middle Ages, and within the Catholic tradition up to Monsignor Ryan’s work in the twentieth century, the theory of economic justice was thought to be composed of two major parts, distributive and commutative justice—with the latter presenting rules of justice that applied to the exchange of goods and services. The right to participate in the production of wealth must have seemed so natural, so innate in human beings, that no need was felt to specify it in writing. With the progressive closure of the commons, the full development of a monetary economy, and the propensity to cluster immense concentrations of wealth in a few hands, the economic conditions of the world have, indeed, changed. The right to be an active participant, rather than being relegated to the margin of economic life is a right that needs to be asserted.
Implementation of the requirements of participative justice is imperative today. Taking the lead from the seminal economic policy analysis of Louis O. Kelso,14 this addition to the theory of economic justice can be justified from many points of view. Its moral rationale can be most clearly found in the social teaching of the Roman Catholic Church. In Centesimus Annus, for instance, Pope John Paul II calls for a “society of free work, of enterprise and of participation.”15 In the preceding paragraph he specifies: “Inseparable from that required ‘something’ (which is due to man because he is man) is the possibility to survive and at the same time to make an active contribution to the common good of humanity.”16
Some of the legal rationale for this addition is provided by Nozick with his principle of “justice in acquisition.”17 The economic rationale can be found in the revision of Keynes’ model first envisaged by this writer in the summer of 1965, and gradually developed ever since. This work yields the equivalence of production to distribution to consumption.18 In accordance with these results the test is as follows: Can the proposed system of rights be justified, through a series of iterations, by the requirements of participative, distributive, and commutative justice?
All too briefly, without the exercise of the proposed four rights, people are not free to participate in the economic process. They are not put in a position of parity in relation to the apportionment of shares in the process of the distribution of wealth. If people do not participate in the production process or are at a disadvantage in the process of the distribution of wealth, then they are automatically at a disadvantage in the process of the exchange of wealth. It would be naive to see the latter set of needs as involving only problems of consumerism; one must enlarge the scope to encompass problems of monopoly and hoarding of wealth. Note Monsignor John A. Ryan’s major work, Distributive Justice: The Right and Wrong of Our Present Distribution of Wealth,19 where he builds on the solid tradition of the past but without ignoring the problems that are still with us today. For instance, this work contains a legal and economic analysis of the minimum wage that is far superior to anything existing in the current literature on the subject.20
In summary, the proposed four economic rights offer the opportunity to complete the structure of the theory of economic justice. The structure can be built upon three planks: participative justice, distributive justice, and commutative justice. But the three component parts of the structure do not operate sequentially. As in a physical structure, they operate synchronously, and the theory becomes a powerful engine of decision and analysis.
Conclusion
There are many indications today that, while public
struggles over the last few centuries were mostly concerned with issues of
political justice, the current struggle is one of economic justice.
Foundational to this struggle is the issue of defining economic rights. This
article has sought to define these rights as rights of access to essential
resources in the process of production, distribution, and the exchange of
wealth. It is through access to those resources that one creates property and
property rights. By regressing the search of the legal title of ownership to
present wealth, one is led to the realization that this was the reality in the
ancient past as it still is today.
The practical thrust of this essay consists in transforming the fact of access to economic resources into the right of access to economic resources. Rich and poor alike—the rich to an obviously greater degree than the poor—live in a legal regimen that is one of privilege. They acquire access to economic resources as a fact—not as a right. This is the ultimate source of instability in the modern polity. The fact of access has to be transformed into a universal right. If rich and poor alike are to live under a regimen of laws, economic rights have to be defined and exercised universally.
This article has sought to provide an understanding of basic economic needs that are met by those rights. It has also described an understanding of the legal characteristics of economic rights. Throughout we have suggested that the theory of economic justice should be seen as composed of participative justice, distributive justice, and commutative justice—three planks that have to be treated not as three sequential segments but as three synchronous parts whose requirements are either satisfied simultaneously or not at all.21
Notes
1
Daniel Rush Finn, “Catholic Social Thought on
Property: An Urgent Need for Extension andRenewal.” Paper presented at the
conference on “The Legacy of Msgr. John A. Ryan,” University of Saint Thomas,
1995.
2
Carmine Gorga, “The Revised Keynes’ Model,” Atlantic Economic Journal 10 (September
1982):
52; “Bold New Directions in
Politics and Economics,” The Humane
Economy Newsletter 12 (March 1991): 3–6, 12; “Quality Assurance: Internal
and External Financing Opportunities,” in Quality
Control and Quality Assurance for Seafood, eds. Gilbert Sylvia, Ann L.
Shriver, and Michael T. Morrisey (Corvallis, Oreg.: Oregon State University,
1994), 158–63; “Four Economic Rights: Social Renewal Through Economic Justice
For All,” Social Justice Review 85
(January/February 1994): 3–6; Carmine Gorga and Norman G. Kurland, “The
Productivity Standard: A True Golden Standard,” in Every Worker An Owner: A Revolutionary Free Enterprise Challenge to
Marxism, ed. Dawn M. Kurland (Washington, D.C.: Center for Economic and
Social Justice, 1987), 83–6; Carmine Gorga and Stuart B. Weeks,
“Fisheries Renewal: A Renewal
of the Soul of Business,” The Catholic
Social Science Review 2 (1997): 145–62.
3
Immanuel Kant, “Philosophy of Law,” in The Great Legal Philosophers: Selected
Readings in Jurisprudence, ed. Clarence Morris (Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1959).
4
Ibid., 252.
5
Giuseppe Mazzini, The
Duties of Man (London: Chapman and Hall, 1862).
6
Oliver Wendall Holmes, “Uncollected Letters,” in The Wisdom of the Supreme Court, ed.
Percival E. Jackson (Norman, Okla.: University of Oklahoma Press, 1962), 398.
7
John Rawls, A
Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), 12,
72, 136, 538.
8
Robert Nozick, Anarchy,
State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 238.
9
Ibid.
10
Alan Gewirth, “Economic Justice: Concepts and
Criteria,” in Economic Justice: Private
Rights and Public Responsibilities, ed. Kenneth Kipnis and Diana T. Meyers
(Totowa, N.J.: Rowman & Allanheld, 1985).
11
Ibid., 19.
12
Rex Martin, Rawls
and Rights (Lawrence, Kans.: University of Kansas Press, 1985), 114–8, 129.
13 Finn, “Catholic Social Thought on Property.”
14
Louis O. Kelso and Mortimer Adler, The Capitalist Manifesto (New York:
Random House, 1958), chap. 5; Louis O. Kelso and Patricia Hetter, Two–Factor Theory: The Economics of Reality
(New York:
Vintage Books, 1967), 10, 28,
32.
15
John Paul II, Encyclical Letter Centesimus Annus (May 15, 1991), no. 35.
16
Ibid., no. 34.
17
Nozick, Anarchy,
State, and Utopia, 150ff., esp. 168.
18
Gorga, “The Revised Keynes’ Model.”
19
John A. Ryan, Distributive
Justice: The Right and Wrong of Our Present Distribution of Wealth (New
York: Macmillan and Company, 1942 [orig. 1916]).
20
Ibid., 249–302. The historic emphasis there is on the
living wage.
21
I would like to acknowledge Professor Michael J.
Naughton, who invited me to participate inthe conference on “The Legacy of
Msgr. John A. Ryan,” University of Saint Thomas, 1995, and Professor Robert G.
Kennedy, who exhibited enormous patience with my unexpected delays in
completing this article. I have benefited from the constructive criticism of
Janis D. Stelluto, David E. Stephens, Stuart B. Weeks, and David S. Wise.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)
A Declaration of Economic Interdependence
In the age of Atomism, The Somist Institute's mission is to reinsert men and women in the social context. This mission is composed of m...
-
Journal of Markets & Morality 2, no. 1(Spring 1999), 88-101 Copyright © 1999 Center for Economic Personalism Toward the Definitio...
-
Originally published at http://rio20.net/en/documentos/ethics-in-concordian-economics/ Documentos February 19 2012 E...
-
In the age of Atomism, The Somist Institute's mission is to reinsert men and women in the social context. This mission is composed of m...